“Agreement” suggests several possibilities, including a
contract, shared understanding, amity. More is implied than absence of
conflict. At least, in terms of contract, an agreement suggests that two minds
have met, reached an understanding, and have a planned course of conduct.
Volumes of law -- both statutes and judicial decisions -- exist as a testament
to the value of agreements and the imperfections inherent in them.
“Constitution,” like “agreement,” suggests several possible
meanings, including the makeup of individual organization, and more often, a
plan of government for an organization, including private organizations like
clubs and associations, and public ones like corporations and governments.
Volumes of law, and of history, exist as a testament to the value of
constitutions and the imperfections inherent in them.
For two and a quarter centuries, the American people have
existed together in a union of states. Throughout that time, every American’s
lives under the terms of two constitutions: their own state Constitution and
the United States Constitution. During that period, state constitutions have
been amended by the will of the people. In addition, the U.S. Constitution has
been amended 27 times. Changes addressed a myriad of matters, from voting ages
to taxation to presidential succession.
All these amendments, changing this scope and terms of state
and federal Constitutions, reflect the exercise of popular sovereignty by
electoral majorities. Among the means by which constitutions may be changed,
amendment by the exercise of popular will, at least in the view of Abraham
Lincoln, was the only approach consonant with a popular republican form of
government. In his first inaugural address, Abraham Lincoln responded to the
popular fear in southern states and that the ascendancy of Republican president
would threaten the desire of the southern states to maintain their
institutions, including slavery, against the popular will of the northern
states.
To get to his point, Lincoln
had to speak with care about a decision of the Supreme Court, Dred Scott v. Sanford, in which the
Supreme Court had held that the Congress acted unconstitutionally when it
regulated the institution of slavery in federal territories that had not yet
been admitted as states to the union. In Lincoln ’s
view, the Dred Scott Court had, essentially,
usurped the role of the Congress in representing the will of the People:
Is it true, then, that any right
plainly written in the Constitution has been denied? I think not. Happily, the human
mind is so constituted that no party can reach to the audacity of doing this.
Think, if you can, of a single instance in which a plainly written provision of
the Constitution has ever been denied. If by the mere force of numbers a
majority should deprive a minority of any clearly written constitutional right,
it might in a moral point of view justify revolution; certainly would if such
right were a vital one. But such is not our case. All the vital rights of
minorities and of individuals are so plainly assured to them by affirmations
and negations, guaranties and prohibitions, in the Constitution that
controversies never arise concerning them. But no organic law can ever be
framed with a provision specifically applicable to every question which may occur
in practical administration. No foresight can anticipate nor any document of
reasonable length contain express provisions for all possible questions. Shall
fugitives from labor be surrendered by national or by State authority? The
Constitution does not expressly say. May Congress prohibit slavery in the
Territories? The Constitution does not expressly say. Must Congress protect
slavery in the Territories? The Constitution does not expressly say.
From questions of this class spring all
our constitutional controversies, and we divide upon them into majorities and
minorities. If the minority will not acquiesce, the majority must, or the
Government must cease. There is no other alternative, for continuing the
Government is acquiescence on one side or the other. If a minority in such case
will secede rather than acquiesce, they make a precedent which in turn will
divide and ruin them, for a minority of their own will secede from them
whenever a majority refuses to be controlled by such minority. For instance, why
may not any portion of a new confederacy a year or two hence arbitrarily secede
again, precisely as portions of the present Union
now claim to secede from it? All who cherish disunion sentiments are now being
educated to the exact temper of doing this.
Is there such perfect identity of
interests among the States to compose a new union as to produce harmony only
and prevent renewed secession?
Plainly the central idea of secession
is the essence of anarchy. A majority held in restraint by constitutional checks
and limitations, and always changing easily with deliberate changes of popular
opinions and sentiments, is the only true sovereign of a free people. Whoever
rejects it does of necessity fly to anarchy or to despotism. Unanimity is
impossible. The rule of a minority, as a permanent arrangement, is wholly
inadmissible; so that, rejecting the majority principle, anarchy or despotism
in some form is all that is left.
Only a rugged individualist or an oligarch would argue
against such republican exercises of electoral will. Nonetheless, such
individualists and oligarchs have objected to these constitutions and these
amendments. Merely objecting to them would mark them as malcontents but leave
our republic intact. Contentment is not, however, a signal feature of a
malcontent.
Over the course of our two century experiment in republican
democracy, constitutional malcontents have grown to rely more and more on one
sure source of recourse: judges. Consider, for example, one such case of an
early malcontent.
In the waning days of the administration of Pres. John
Adams, William Marbury received an appointment as a justice of the peace in the
District of Columbia .
As Adams administration ended the
commissioning papers for Marbury were prepared, but never delivered. After
Thomas Jefferson took office, and James Madison was installed as secretary of
state, Marbury sought his commission papers from Madison . Madison refused to deliver the commission
papers to Marbury. Without the commissioning papers Marbury did not validly
hold his office as justice of the peace.
To put Marbury’s demand to Jefferson
in perspective, imagine a circumstance in which, in the waning days of the
George W Bush administration, a Jewish judicial nominee was confirmed by the
Senate. Further, imagine that a commission embodying Bush’s nomination and the
Senate’s consent was prepared. Yet, through oversight or neglect, the
commission was never issued to the nominee I know oath of office administered.
On inaugural day, picture newly installed Pres. Obama entering the Oval Office
for the first time as president of the United States . Take in his pleasant
surprise on discovering the as yet unknown transmitted commission sitting on
his desk, a Post-it note attached to it stating, “Please transmit to nominee.”
Even were Obama a nice man, a decent sort, it asks too much
of him that he installed in office-for life-a judicial officer selected by the
previous president. The likelihood that such a nominee would meet the
ideological preferences of a president of a different political party is
laughably small. So, like Jefferson did, you
can easily see that Obama would decline to transmit the judicial commission.
In Marbury’s case, being denied the all-but-transmitted
commission proved too much. Marbury acted. He filed suit against James Madison,
Thomas Jefferson’s Secretary of State. Marbury demanded that the court issue an
order requiring Madison
to grant the commission prepared during John Adams administration. Because
Congress had authorized such suits to be filed in the Supreme Court, rather
than in a Trial Court, Marbury filed suit at the Supreme Court.
The Supreme Court dismissed Marbury suit.
In its view, Congress across the boundary in the
Constitution by its enactment of the Judiciary act. Congress enacted the
Judiciary Act, exercising an express power set out in the Constitution: “The judicial power of the United States
shall be vested in one Supreme Court, and in such inferior courts as the
Congress may from time to time ordain and establish.” In the case of the
Judiciary Act, Congress was in fact establishing and ordaining inferior courts.
In addition to establishing lower tribunals, however Congress had also enacted
a provision in the law allowing litigants to seek writs of mandamus at the Supreme
Court.
Since its decision, Marbury
v. Madison has come to stand for another principle. The Supreme Court
asserted as part of its discussion in Marbury that it had supremacy over
Congress and the president in deciding the meaning of the words of the United
States Constitution. Such an assertion should have provoked the other branches
to immediate response. The decision in Marbury, however, favored Jefferson ’s administration in its treatment of Marbury,
so it’s provocative dictum was without present harm. In Congress, the House of
Representatives had selected Jefferson for
president, so again little motivation existed for an immediate reaction there.
Thus, the Supreme Court’s otherwise controversial claim -- that between it and
the other branches of the federal government, it was the ultimate arbiter of
the meaning of the Constitution -- went unanswered.
Now, not every suit fits the mode of the constitutional
malcontent. When Acme Company sues John Doe for payment on services rendered, a
court may have to interpret the contract. When a man is prosecuted for crime,
the meaning of a criminal statute may have to be construed. These judicial
extractions of meaning-- from statutes, from contracts, and from constitutions
-- are ordinary in the course of adjudication.
The hallmark of the constitutional malcontent is the search
for a new or contradictory meaning of the Constitution via judicial
decision-making, rather than via amendment of the Constitution. You know the
obvious case: Jane Roe, suing to prevent the State of Texas
from enforcing its long-standing statutory ban on abortion, and Mary Doe, suing
to prevent the State of Georgia
from enforcing its modern-day reformed abortion laws. No honest broker of American history claims
that the United States Constitution literally guarantees the right to have an
abortion. Yet, at the time of Roe v. Wade, there was NO likelihood
that an amendment to the US Constitution could be ratified that would legalize
abortion broadly as did Harry Blackmun’s hit piece. So, rather than engage hearts and minds of
Americans in a longer term conversation about liberty, equality, women’s
health, or related issues, Roe and Doe were made the frontispiece of the
pro-abortion lobby’s frontal assault on the Constitution, an assault welcomed
by a complicit Supreme Court already long comfortable in its assumed role as
final arbiter of the Constitution’s meaning.
Still other cases, ripped from today’s headlines, mark the
newest ventures into the field of the amendment-free amendment of the Constitution. These are the cases seeking a federal
constitutional home for a right to overturn State laws defining marriage, even
State Constitutions defining marriage.
These most recent cases, now a string of successful appeals to federal
judges to re-read the federal Constitution in a way that rejects the
long-settled statutory definitions of marriage in virtually every State of the Union . These
litigants are the latest constitutional malcontents. They cannot converse with the People and
persuade hearts and minds. But they can get
themselves to a courthouse and find respite there.
What should worry the malcontent, but which they never seem to grasp, is the danger of the precedent involved in propping up this false judicial oligarchy. Now we do NOT rule ourselves by common agreement. We are ruled, and overruled, by the preferences of unelected micro-minorities: appointees who enjoy lifetime employment, undiminished income, and freedom from the democratic urge to engage. These judges DICTATE, they do not discuss; they COMMAND, they do not invite. When such a judge should turn on them, how will they save themselves? By recourse to the People, whose laws they reject, whose judgments regarding social convention they reject? By recourse to judges, whose autocracy is without pity?
What should worry the malcontent, but which they never seem to grasp, is the danger of the precedent involved in propping up this false judicial oligarchy. Now we do NOT rule ourselves by common agreement. We are ruled, and overruled, by the preferences of unelected micro-minorities: appointees who enjoy lifetime employment, undiminished income, and freedom from the democratic urge to engage. These judges DICTATE, they do not discuss; they COMMAND, they do not invite. When such a judge should turn on them, how will they save themselves? By recourse to the People, whose laws they reject, whose judgments regarding social convention they reject? By recourse to judges, whose autocracy is without pity?
Ultimately, if the Nation is to survive, there has to be
AGREEMENT under a CONSTITUTION. But that
agreement cannot bear the weight of a Nation unless it is the voluntary
agreement of minds that have shared values and common purposes. The day when such an outcome is possible
seems to be something visible only in the rear view mirror. Still, inviting the conversation may be the
way to discover whether that is so.